Kamis, 03 Mei 2018

Game Theory The Science of Decision-Making

Game Theory The Science of Decision-Making
When youre hanging out with your friends,
you probably dont think too hard about the math behind the decisions youre making. But theres a whole field of math  and
science  that applies to social interactions. Its called Game Theory. Game theory was pioneered in the 1950s by
mathematician John Nash, the guy from that Russell Crowe played in A Beautiful Mind.

But game theory isnt about games the way
we normally think about them. Instead, a game is any interaction between
multiple people in which each persons payoff is affected by the decisions made by others. So, sure, that could apply to a game of poker. But it could also apply to practically any
situation where people get together and get up in each others business.

Like, did you interact with anyone today? Well, you can probably analyze the decisions
you made using game theory. Game theory is incredibly wide-ranging, and
its used all the time by economists, political scientists, biologists, military tacticians,
and psychologists, to name just a few. Game theory has two main branches: cooperative,
and noncooperative, or competitive, game theory. Noncooperative game theory covers competitive
social interactions, where there will be some winners  and some losers.

Probably the most famous thought experiment
in competitive game theory is the Prisoners Dilemma. The prisoners dilemma describes a game
a social interaction  that involves two prisoners. Well call them Wanda and Fred. Wanda and Fred were arrested fleeing from
the scene of a crime, and based on the evidence the police have already collected, theyre
going to have to spend two years in jail.

But, the DA wants more. So he offers them both a deal: if you confess
to the crime, and your partner does not, youll be granted immunity for cooperating. Youll be free to go. Your partner, though, will serve ten years
in jail.

If you both confess, and dish up loads of
dirt about each other, then you will both end up spending five years in jail. But if neither of you confess, youll both
spend only two years in jail. Those are their options. Then, Wanda and Fred are split up.

They dont know what their partner is going
to do. They have to make their decisions independently. Now, Wanda and Fred they- theyve had some
wild times stealing diamonds or whatever, but they dont have any special loyalty
to each other. Theyre not brother and sister; theyre
hardened criminals.

Fred has no reason to think Wanda wont
stab him in the back, and vice versa. Competitive game theory arranges their choices
and their potential consequences into a grid that looks like this: If both Wanda and Fred choose not to confess,
theyll both serve two years. In theory, this is the best overall outcome. Combined, they would spend as little time
in prison as possible.

But  that immunity sounds pretty good. If one of them chooses to confess, and the
other one doesnt, the snitch gets to walk. Then the math looks like this: Thats the problem: Wanda and Fred have
no reason to trust each other. Wanda might consider not confessing, because
if Fred doesnt confess either, they both only serve two years.

If they could really trust each other, that
would be their best bet. But Wanda cant be sure that Fred wont
snitch. He has a LOT to gain by confessing. If he does decide to confess, and she keeps
silent, shes risking ten years in jail while he goes free.

Compared to that, the five years theyd
get for both turning on each other doesnt sound so bad. And that is game theorys solution: they
should both confess and rat each other out. So, right now youre thinking, Wow, game
theory is a jerk. But it actually makes sense.

That square in the grid where they both confess
is the only outcome thats reached whats known as Nash Equilibrium. This is a key concept in competitive game
theory. A player in a game has found Nash Equilibrium
when they make the choice that leaves them better off no matter what their opponents
decide to do. If Wanda confesses, and Fred does not confess
shes better off.

She gets to walk! By confessing, she went from serving two years
in prison to serving none. If Fred does confess...Shes still better
off. If shed kept her mouth shut, shed be
spending ten years in prison. Now, she only has to serve five.

Sure, if she decides not to confess, and Fred
keeps his pinky promise too, they both get out in two years. But thats an unstable state. Because Wanda cant trust Fred- she doesnt
know what hes going to do. This is not a cooperative game: all of the
players stand to gain from stabbing each other in the back.

The Prisoners Dilemma is just one example
of a competitive game, but the basic idea behind its solution applies to all kinds of
situations. Generally, when youre competing with others,
it makes sense to choose the course of action that benefits you the most no matter what
everyone else decides to do. Then there are cooperative games, where every
player has agreed to work together toward a common goal. This could be anything from a group of friends
deciding how to split up the cost to pay the bill at a restaurant, to a coalition of nations
deciding how to divvy up the burden of stopping climate change.

In game theory, a coalition is what you call
a group of players in a cooperative game. When it comes to cooperative games, game theorys
main question is how much each player should contribute to the coalition, and how much
they should benefit from it. In other words, it tries to determine whats
fair. Where competitive game theory has the Nash
Equilibrium, cooperative game theory has whats called the Shapley Value.

The Shapley Value is a method of dividing
up gains or costs among players according to the value of their individual contributions. It works by applying several axioms. Number one: the contribution of each player
is determined by what is gained or lost by removing them from the game. This is called their marginal contribution.

Lets say that every day this week, you
and your friends are baking cookies. When you get sick for a day, probably from
eating too many cookies, the group produces fifty fewer cookies than they did on the days
that you were there. So your marginal contribution to the coalition,
every day, is fifty cookies. Number two: Interchangeable players have equal
value.

If two parties bring the same things to the
coalition, they should have to contribute the same amount, and should be rewarded for
their contributions equally. Like if two people order the same thing at
the restaurant, they should pay the same amount of the bill. If two workers have the same skills, they
should receive the same wages. Number three: Dummy players have zero value.

In other words, if a member of a coalition
contributes nothing, then they should receive nothing. This ones controversial. It could mean that if you go to dinner with
your friends, but you dont order anything, you shouldnt have to chip in when the bill
comes. Which seems fair, in that case.

But it could also mean that if somebody cant
contribute to the work force, they shouldnt receive any compensation. The thing is, there are good reasons why somebody
might not be able to contribute: maybe theyre on maternity leave. Or they got in an accident. Or they have some kind of a disability.

In situations like that, the coalition might
want to pay something out to them in spite of them not being able to contribute. The fourth axiom says that if a game has multiple
parts, cost or payment should be decomposed across those parts. This just means that, for example, if you
did a lot of work for the group on Monday, but you slacked off on Tuesday, your rewards
on each day should be different. Or if you ordered a salad one night, but a
steak dinner the next, you probably should pay more on the second night.

In other words, its not always fair to
use the same solution every time. The numbers should be reviewed regularly,
so that the coalition can make adjustments. If you find a way of dividing up costs or
divvying up payment to all of the players that satisfies all of those axioms, thats
the Shapley value. The Shapley value can be expressed mathematically
like this: Which, yeah, is kind of complicated.

But we can break down the concepts into something
less  mathy. Lets go back to looking at cookies. Youre baking cookies, and your friend is
baking cookies. In an hour, you can bake ten cookies when
youre working alone.

Your friend though, is like, a cookie wizard,
and in the same hour, working alone, he can bake twenty cookies. When you decide to team up. When you work together, you streamline your
process. One person can mix up all the batter at once
or whatever, which saves you a lot of time.

So after an hour, you have forty cookies. But if youd each been working alone, youd
only have made 30 cookies in the same hour. Then you sell each of those cookies for a
dollar. Now youve got forty dollars.

How do you divide up the loot? The Shapley value equation tells you to think
about it like this: If you take the fact that you can make ten
cookies an hour, and subtract them from the total, that gives your friend credit for the
other thirty cookies. Thats what happens when you remove your
friend from the system: their marginal contribution to you is thirty cookies. But if you take the fact that your friend
can make twenty cookies an hour, and subtract that from the total, that gives YOU credit
for twenty cookies. Because if youre removed from your friends
cookie-making system, your marginal contribution to them is twenty cookies.

In the first case, your value to the coalition
was only ten cookies. But in the second case, your value to the
coalition is twenty cookies. According to the Shapley value equation, you
should average those two numbers together. Ten plus twenty is thirty, divided by two
is fifteen.

So, the Shapley value equation says that you
should get fifteen dollars, and your friend should get twenty-five. This method can be scaled up to coalitions
with hundreds of players, by finding their marginal contributions to every other player
and then calculating the average of all of those numbers. Interactions can get much more complicated
than the Prisoners Dilemma or baking cookies, so theres a lot more to game theory. But it comes down to this: in a competitive
situation, game theory can tell you how to be smart.

And in a cooperative situation, game theory
can tell you how to be fair. Thanks for watching this episode of SciShow,
which was brought to you by our patrons on Patreon who are people who contribute to SciShow,
even though they dont have to so that it can be free for everyone. And right now, were taking all of the money
that we raise on Patreon between now and the end of the year -- so from September to December
-- and were going to put that toward a brand-new series here on Youtube. Its going to be a new channel under the
SciShow brand.

It's either going to be SciShow Life, SciShow
Health, or SciShow Psych. We here at the SciShow offices want to do
all of those things but we can only do one of them so our patrons on Patreon are deciding. If you want to be one of those people or if
you just want to help contribute, you can go to patreon.Com/scishow. And of course, if you just want to watch this,
get smarter with us, you can go to youtube.Com/scishow and subscribe!.

Tidak ada komentar:

Posting Komentar